My lectures on Behavioural Finance

Flattr this!

I’ve just com­plet­ed sec­ond year of my sub­ject Behav­iour­al Finance at the Uni­ver­si­ty of West­ern Syd­ney. This is of course a non-tra­di­tion­al subject–meaning non-Effi­cient-Mar­kets-Hypoth­e­sis–but even here I take a non-stan­dard approach. While I have great respect for the work of Kah­ne­man and Tver­sky on behav­iour­al eco­nom­ics, I argue that much of the sub­se­quent work is mis-direct­ed, because of a cru­cial mis­in­ter­pre­ta­tion of the orig­i­nal work on expect­ed util­i­ty by von Neu­mann and Mor­gen­stern.

Much of the stan­dard behav­iour­al finance lit­er­a­ture shows that indi­vid­ual behav­iour vio­lates the pre­cepts of expect­ed util­i­ty the­o­ry when faced with a choice between two hypo­thet­i­cal options, and then devel­ops some mod­i­fied util­i­ty func­tion that fits the actu­al behav­iour. The options are nor­mal­ly pre­sent­ed in this man­ner:

  • 1. Choose between
    • A.$1000 with cer­tain­ty; OR
    • B. 90% odds of $2000 & 10% odds of -$1000
  • 2. Choose between
    • A. $0 with cer­tain­ty; OR
    • B. 50% odds of $150 and 50% odds of -$100
  • 3. Choose between
    • A. -$100 with cer­tain­ty; OR
    • B. 50% odds of $50; 50% odds of -$200

It is alleged that a ratio­nal per­son accord­ing to expect­ed util­i­ty the­o­ry would choose B in all 3 cas­es, since the expect­ed val­ue of B exceeds A every time. The expect­ed val­ue is cal­cu­lat­ed sim­ply by mul­ti­ply­ing the val­ue of each out­come by the prob­a­bil­i­ties. Thus the val­ues above are

  • 1. Choose between
    • A: $1000
    • B. .9 times $2000 + .1 times -$1000 = 1800 — 100 = 1700
  • 2. Choose between
    • A. $0
    • B. .5 times $150 — .5 times $100 = $75 — 50 = 25
  • 3. Choose between
    • A. -$100
    • B.  .5 times $50 — .5 times $200 = $25 — 100 = -$75

How­ev­er, when exper­i­ments are con­duct­ed, the major­i­ty of peo­ple choose option A in choic­es 1 and 2, but B in num­ber 3: they are “irra­tional” twice and ratio­nal once. This sets up all sorts of conun­drums, lead­ing to a range of inter­est­ing prob­lems, and a volu­mi­nous lit­er­a­ture on irra­tional­i­ty, bound­ed ratio­nal­i­ty, risk aver­sion, pref­er­ence rever­sal, and so on. The Wikipedia entry (as at Novem­ber 11 2010) encap­su­lates this per­spec­tive:

The expect­ed util­i­ty hypoth­e­sis, as applied to eco­nom­ics, has lim­it­ed pre­dic­tive accu­ra­cy, sim­ply because in prac­tice, humans do not always behave VNM-ratio­nal­ly. This can be inter­pret­ed as evi­dence that

  • humans are not always ratio­nal, or
  • VNM-ratio­nal­i­ty is not an appro­pri­ate char­ac­ter­i­za­tion of ratio­nal­i­ty, or
  • some com­bi­na­tion of both.

Had von Neu­mann lived to see the devel­op­ment of this the­o­ry, I expect he’d be ques­tion­ing, not human ratio­nal­i­ty in gen­er­al, but the ratio­nal­i­ty of his interpreters–because his con­cept of expect­ed util­i­ty was very dif­fer­ent to how it is now por­trayed in the lit­er­a­ture. The cru­cial dif­fer­ence is that the lit­er­a­ture uses a sub­jec­tive vision of prob­a­bil­i­ty, when this was explic­it­ly reject­ed by von Neu­mann and Mor­gen­stern:

Prob­a­bil­i­ty has often been visu­al­ized as a sub­jec­tive con­cept more or less inthe nature of esti­ma­tion. Since we pro­pose to use it in con­struct­ing anin­di­vid­ual, numer­i­cal esti­ma­tion of util­i­ty, the above view of prob­a­bil­i­ty would­not serve our pur­pose. The sim­plest pro­ce­dure is, there­fore, to insist upon­the alter­na­tive, per­fect­ly well found­ed inter­pre­ta­tion of prob­a­bil­i­ty as fre­quen­cy in long runs.” (von Neu­mann & Mor­gen­stern 1944: 19)

What dif­fer­ence does that make? A lot! Try it with the above three exam­ples: con­sid­er exact­ly the same choic­es, but with the pro­vi­so that whichev­er option you choose you must repeat 100 times:

  • 1. Choose between
    • A. Receiv­ing $1000 with cer­tain­ty 100 times; OR
    • B. 100 gam­bles with 90% odds of $2000 & 10% odds of -$1000
  • 2. Choose between
    • A. Recev­ing $0 with cer­tain­ty 100 times; OR
    • B. 100 gam­bles with 50% odds of $150 and 50% odds of -$100
  • 3. Choose between
    • A. Los­ing -$100 with cer­tain­ty 100 times; OR
    • B. 100 gam­bles with 50% odds of $50; 50% odds of -$200

Now there’s no doubt that option B is the ratio­nal one. The total val­ues of the options are now:

  • 1.
    • A. $100,000
    • B. 100 times (.9 times $2000 — .1 times -$1000) = 100 times ($1,800 — $100) = $180,000 — $10,000 = $170,000
  • 2.
    • A. $0
    • B. 100 times (.5 times $150 — .5 times $100) = 100 times ($75 — $50) = $2,500

3.

  • A. -$10,000
  • B. 100 times (.5 times $50 — .5 times -$200) = 100 times ($25 — $100) = -$7,500

Do the sums and you’d have to be irra­tional (or very bad at arith­metic) to choose A over B.

The dif­fer­ence between the way the lit­er­a­ture has inter­pret­ed von Neu­mann and Mor­gen­stern and the way they intend­ed their work to be used is that, in their mod­el, the con­sumer actu­al­ly gets the Expect­ed Val­ue of the gam­ble, because if you take a gam­ble 100 times, the out­come is very like­ly to be close to the pre­dict­ed odds. If on the oth­er hand you under­take a gam­ble only once, you don’t get the Expect­ed Val­ue: you get either one option or the oth­er, and prob­a­bil­i­ty can tell you which is more like­ly, but it can’t tell you which one you’ll actu­al­ly get.

Con­se­quent­ly I see much of the behav­iour­al eco­nom­ics & finance lit­er­a­ture as inter­est­ing, but wrong-headed–and is so often the case in eco­nom­ics, using a def­i­n­i­tion of “ratio­nal” that is seri­ous­ly irra­tional. My sub­ject there­fore devotes a mod­icum of time to the stan­dard lit­er­a­ture before mov­ing into what I see as a more real­is­tic approach, of con­sid­er­ing what the macro behav­iour of the finance sec­tor actu­al­ly is. This leads ulti­mate­ly to Min­sky’s Finan­cial Insta­bil­i­ty Hypoth­e­sis and the “Great Reces­sion”.

All my lec­tures (in pow­er­point for­mat) are linked below, as well as MP3 record­ings of the lec­tures and, in some cas­es, FLV record­ings of my pre­sen­ta­tion. I had some hard­ware and soft­ware has­sles while doing all this; hope­ful­ly I’ll be able to post a more com­plete set of these next year.

Lecture 01: Economic Behaviour

Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Lecture 02: Market Behaviour

Part 1 Demand: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Part 2 Sup­ply: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Lecture 03: Theoretical Financial Markets Behaviour

Part 1: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Part 2: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Lecture 04: Actual Financial Markets Behaviour

Part 1: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Part 2: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Lecture 05: Fractal Markets Hypothesis

Part 1: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast

 

Lecture 06: Inefficient Markets Hypothesis

Pow­er­point

Lecture 07: Statistics on money

Part 1: Pow­er­point

Part 2: Pow­er­point

Lecture 08: Endogenous money

Part 1: Pow­er­point

Part 2: Pow­er­point

Lecture 09: Modelling endogenous money

Part 1: Pow­er­point

Part 2: Pow­er­point

Lecture 10: Extending endogenous money

Part 1: Pow­er­point

Part 2: Pow­er­point

Lecture 11: The Financial Instability Hypothesis

Part 1: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast 

| Open Play­er in New Win­dow

Part 2: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast 

| Open Play­er in New Win­dow

Lecture 12: The “Global Financial Crisis”

Part 1: Pow­er­point

Part 2: Pow­er­point

Steve Keen’s Debt­watch Pod­cast 

| Open Play­er in New Win­dow

Bookmark the permalink.

About Steve Keen

I am Professor of Economics and Head of Economics, History and Politics at Kingston University London, and a long time critic of conventional economic thought. As well as attacking mainstream thought in Debunking Economics, I am also developing an alternative dynamic approach to economic modelling. The key issue I am tackling here is the prospect for a debt-deflation on the back of the enormous private debts accumulated globally, and our very low rate of inflation.